Not All Explanations Predict Satisfactorily, and Not All Good Predictions Explain

نویسنده

  • Klaus G. Troitzsch
چکیده

This short comment on Epstein's (2008) paper and on the response by Thompson and Derr (2008) argues that the symmetry between explanation and prediction cannot satisfactorily be discussed without making clear what prediction means—depending on which connotations the authors have with 'prediction' their arguments can or cannot be accepted. 1.1 Both Epstein (2008) and the authors of response (Thompson and Derr 2008, this issue of JASSS) miss one important point: Both take "prediction" as a term with a fixed and unambiguous meaning—which it is not. Epstein seems to understand prediction in the sense this word has in the sentence "the orbits of the planets will never be predicted." By the way, in this argumentation he forgets that 2000 years before Newton solar and lunar eclipses could be predicted with surprisingly high precision with a model which we now find wrong (which means that a good prediction is not necessarily a good explanation). Thompson's and Derr's reply accepts a much weaker meaning of "predict" as they call "earthquakes occur" a prediction (for which no theory is necessary, after the first earthquake that ever occurred it was clear to humankind that such things happen). Of course, the predictive power of plate tectonics is even higher as it predicts that in certain parts of the planet earthquakes will be more frequent than in other regions. This finding makes it necessary to argue that there are at least three different meanings of prediction, namely as an answer to three quite different questions (see Troitzsch 1997, p. 46): 1 "Which kinds of behaviour can be expected [from a system like this] under arbitrarily given parameter combinations and initial conditions? 2 Which kind of behaviour will a given target system (whose parameters and previous states may or may not have been precisely measured) display in the near future? 3 Which state will the target system reach in the near future, again given parameters and previous states which may or may not have been precisely measured?" 1.2 With this distinction between different kinds of prediction, the controversy between Epstein and his critics is easily ended: Any kind of good explanation, under all circumstances will yield a prediction of type 1 (and perhaps also of type 2), but not every good explanation will yield a prediction if type 3. The prediction of type 3 can even be subdivided in a stochastic or statistical version and a deterministic one (see Troitzsch 1997, p. 46-47): 3a Which are the expected value and the confidence interval around the expected value of the state the target system will reach in the near future, again given parameters and previous states which may or may not have been precisely measured? 3b Which exact value will the state of the target system have at a certain point of time in the near future, again given parameters and previous states which have been precisely measured? (This version was not even mentioned in Troitzsch 1997 and seems to be excluded in Epstein's paper, paragraph 1.8, as well!) The prediction of a solar or lunar eclipse is obviously of type 3b, as everybody knows who ever observed one of these phenomena. The prediction of the temperature at some time during the next few days is obviously of type 3a, as we know from weather forecasts on the TV (where they usually show the trajectory of the expected temperature for the next few days, surrounded by a funnel which shows the growing confidence interval). 1.3 But there is another claim to make: it is not the case that Carl Hempel's symmetry hypothesis was never contested. Some fifty years ago there was a long discussion (see Scriven 1959 and Grünbaum 1962, and see also Stegmüller 1966, where he points to the vagueness and ambiguity of the terms explanation and prediction, and Stegmüller 1969, chapter II, with a very detailed analysis of explanation, retrodiction and prediction). Hempel's argumentation with respect to the symmetry thesis after this discussion (Hempel 1965) is much more detailed, and he argues only that an adequate explanation is a potential prediction (a thesis which he defends strongly) and that an adequate prediction is a potential explanation (here he is more retentive, in principle accepting that the precise predictions of solar eclipses by ancient astronomers were based on wrong explanations). The problem here is the word "adequate". It is quite obvious that his notion of adequacy is similar to Zeigler's (1985, p. 5) "structural validity" since whenever a model is structurally valid ("if it not only reproduces the observed real system behaviour, but truly reflects the way in which the real system operates to produce its behaviour") it can be expected to make predictions of any of the types 1 through 3a (of type 3b only in the entirely deterministic case)—but even non-adequate explanations are potential and even good predictions: see the case of solar and lunar eclipses predicted by Babylonian astronomers. 1.4 In the case of living, cognitive and social systems (and in other complex systems as well) cause-effect relations are rarely as simple as in the examples referred to by Hempel, Grünbaum, Scriven and Stegmüller mentioned above (their arguments are mainly about artillery, astronomy, hydraulics, only Scriven refers to medicine, namely the case of late symptoms of a particular disease which may or may not occur—but Scriven is rather an opponent of the symmetry thesis). In these complex systems sometimes the same effect can be produced by different combinations of different causes (see the discussion in Hempel 1965, footnote 46, where he argues that in the medical cases referred to by opponents of the symmetry thesis the available information is often not sufficient to explain the observed outcome). And this is in line with Epstein's argumentation that "Explanation Does Not Imply Prediction"—if and only if we interpret Epstein's prediction as a prediction of type 3b; if we restrict the meaning of prediction to type-1 or type-2 prediction, then a claim that an explanatory theory can predict is certainly possible.

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

Plato Seeking for “One Real Explanation” in Phaedo

What this essay is to discuss is Plato''s theory of explanation in Phaedo. In this dialogue, we observe that Socrates criticizes both the natural scientists’ explanations and Anaxagoras’ theory of Mind since he thinks they could not explain all things, firstly, in a unitary and, secondary, in a real way. Thence, we are to call what Plato is seeking as his ideal explanation in Phaedo “One Real E...

متن کامل

It's in your nature: a pluralistic folk psychology

I suggest a pluralistic account of folk psychology according to which not all predictions or explanations rely on the attribution of mental states, and not all intentional actions are explained by mental states. This view of folk psychology is supported by research in developmental and social psychology. It is well known that people use personality traits to predict behavior. I argue that trait...

متن کامل

Evaluation of an evaluation

Introduction. Evaluation is a systematic way to improve and make more effective actions that involves procedures which are useful, feasible, ethical, and accurate. Common questions in all evaluations are: do all part of program do well and effective? What is the good functioning? Why the program or its parts do not work well? What are the effects and consequences of the program? Is this progra...

متن کامل

The Intriguing Properties of Model Explanations

Linear approximations to the decision boundary of a complex model have become one of the most popular tools for interpreting predictions. In this paper, we study such linear explanations produced either post-hoc by a few recent methods or generated along with predictions with contextual explanation networks (CENs). We focus on two questions: (i) whether linear explanations are always consistent...

متن کامل

Book Abstract: How to Write an Emergency Plan by David Alexander; Reproduced by Permission

In 2002, David Alexander wrote Principles of Emergency Planning and Management. Long a standard reference work in that book he described the processes of preparing for and responding to disasters, crises, and civil contingencies. He based the work on principles because he wanted to dissociate it from any particular system of emergency management. Then, as now, many books in this subject are tie...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

عنوان ژورنال:
  • J. Artificial Societies and Social Simulation

دوره 12  شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2009